4. Large cardinals and cardinal arithmetic
In section 3 we saw how the powers of singular cardinals (or, at least, of singulars of uncountable cofinality) satisfy strong restrictions. Here I show that similar restrictions hold at large cardinals. There is much more than one could say about this topic, and the results I present should be seen much more like an invitation than a full story. Also, for lack of time, I won’t motivate the large cardinals we will discuss. (In the ideal world, one should probably say a few words about one’s beliefs in large cardinals, since their existence and even their consistency goes beyond what can be done in the standard system I’ll however take their existence for granted, and proceed from there.)
1. Measurable cardinals
Definition 1
is a measurable cardinal iff
and there is a nonprincipal
-complete ultrafilter over
![]()
Recall that is an ultrafilter (over
or on
) iff the following hold:
if
then
- If
then
- For all
either
or else
Conditions 1–3 state that is a filter. Notice that by 2 and 3,
has the finite intersection property. Conversely, any collection of subsets of
with the finite intersection property generates in a natural way a filter.
Condition 4 is the ultrafilter condition. Equivalently, one can request that is maximal under containment (subject to being a filter). The equivalence is an easy consequence of Zorn’s lemma.
An ultrafilter over
is nonprincipal iff
for any
Otherwise, it is principal. Clearly, any ultrafilter over a finite set is principal. On the other hand, any infinite set admits a nonprincipal ultrafilter, in fact, since the collection of subsets of
whose complements have size strictly smaller than
has the finite intersection property, there are uniform ultrafilters over
, i.e., ultrafilters all of whose elements have the same size as
As before, an ultrafilter is
-complete iff any intersection of fewer than
many members of
is in
If
we also say that
is
-complete. Equivalently, by considering complements,
is
-complete iff whenever a union of fewer than
many sets is in
then at least one of the sets in the union is in
Clearly, no nonprincipal ultrafilter over can be
-complete. On the other hand, normality is a stronger requirement than
-completeness.
Homework problem 10. Assume that is a
-complete nonprincipal ultrafilter over some set
Let
be the completeness of
i.e.,
is smallest such that
is not
-complete. Show that
is measurable.
Ulam introduced measurable cardinals by working on a question on Banach. The problem is whether there could be a nontrivial measure space In detail,
and
for any pairwise disjoint sequence of subsets of
The nontriviality condition means several things. First of all, (otherwise, we must have
for all
)
But this is not enough. For consider any set any function
and any (possibly empty, or perhaps nonproper)
-ideal
of subsets of
Then we can set
if
and
if
and certainly
is a measure space. We then say that a measure space
is nontrivial iff it does not arise in this fashion.
Assume that is nontrivial. Let
if
and
otherwise. Let
be the
-ideal generated by the subsets of
of finite measure, and let
be the trivial measure over
generated by
and
Then
for all
but
since we are assuming that
is nontrivial. It follows that there is some
such that
It must then be the case that
and therefore (by definition of
) there is an increasing sequence
of subsets of
such that
and
for all
Necessarily,
for some
and we can define a measure
by setting
Notice that in fact and
for all
By normalizing, we may as well assume that
This shows that the measure problem has a solution iff there is a nontrivial probability space (so in particular
and
) such that
for all
and this is the way in which the question is most commonly posed in the literature.
Let be the additivity of the measure
i.e., the least cardinal
such that the measure of any disjoint union of fewer than
many disjoint subsets of
is the sum of the measures of the sets in the union, understanding that
if there is no such cardinal.
Let be the collection of subsets of
of measure zero. Then
is an ideal. For any ideal
over a set
we can define
as the least cardinality of a collection of sets in
whose union is not in
understanding that
if there is no such cardinal.
If is a probability space, then either
and the space is trivial, or else
is some cardinal
In this latter case, there must be a sequence
of nonempty pairwise disjoint sets in
whose union
is not in
In this case we can define a measure over
as follows: For
let
be the ordinal such that
Let
Then set
Then
is a probability space,
for all
and
is
-additive.
Ulam noticed that in this case an interesting dichotomy happens: Either is nonatomic, meaning that for for all
if
then there is some
such that
in which case
and we say that
is (atomlessly) real-valued measurable, or else
admits an atom
, that necessarily must have size
In this case, for all
either
or
By renormalizing and composing with a bijection, this gives us a probability space
where
for all
and
is
-complete. Letting
is a
-complete nonprincipal ultrafilter over
i.e.,
is measurable.
Conversely, if is measurable and
is a
-complete nonprincipal ultrafilter over
then
the characteristic function of
is an example of such a probability measure
Theorem 2 (Tarski-Ulam) If
is measurable or real-valued measurable, then it is weakly inaccessible. If
is in fact measurable, then it is strong limit and therefore (strongly) inaccessible.
Proof: Fix a witnessing probability so
is
-additive, singletons are null, and
is either nonatomic or bivalued.
is regular. Because, by
-completeness, every bounded subset of
in particular every ordinal below
is null, and therefore
cannot be the union of fewer than
many ordinals below
since any such union has measure zero.
is limit. For this, proceed by contradiction, assuming that
and consider a
Ulam matrix
see Definition 12 in lecture II.5. Arguing just as in the proof of Theorem 13 there, notice that
has measure 1 for all
and by
-completeness of
there must be some
such that
has positive measure.
By the pigeonhole principle, there is some fixed such that
for
many distinct values of
Recall now that
whenever
By the pigeonhole principle again, since
there is some nonzero
such that
for uncountably many ordinals
This is clearly a contradiction.
Assume now that is measurable. Then
is strong limit. Let
be the ultrafilter corresponding to
Let
and suppose that
and
It is enough to see that
for some
since this shows that
is
-complete, so
Notice that for each
there is a (least)
such that
Let
be the function that to each
assigns the corresponding
Then
since
is at least
-complete.
Homework problem 11. Show that if is real-valued measurable then
by showing that
where
is as above. For this, begin by showing that for any
there is some
such that
Of course, Theorem 2 implies that the existence of measurable cardinals is not provable in since if
is strongly inaccessible then
Whether all inaccessible cardinals are measurable is a different story. In fact, if is measurable, then it is the
-th inaccessible cardinal, and one can show much stronger results showing how vast the increment in strength is between both notions. This we will do by means of the ultrapower construction, a key idea in the study of large cardinals.
The reduction indicated above of the measure problem to the question of the existence of a -complete probability space
where singletons are null is probably classical. I followed the approach of David Fremlin, Real-valued measurable cardinals, in Set Theory of the reals, Haim Judah, ed., Israel Mathematical Conference Proceedings 6, Bar-Ilan University (1993), 151–304.
(Typeset using LaTeX2WP. Here is a printable version of this post.)
[…] The study of ultrapowers originates in model theory, although it has found applications both in algebra and in analysis. However, it is accurate to say that it is mainly exploited in set theory. Here I present the basic idea, showing its close connection to the study of measurable cardinals, defined last lecture. […]
[…] The study of ultrapowers originates in model theory, although it has found applications both in algebra and in analysis. However, it is accurate to say that it is mainly exploited in set theory. Here I present the basic idea, showing its close connection to the study of measurable cardinals, defined last lecture. […]