1. The -Rado theorem
Large homogeneous sets (of size or larger) can be ensured, at the cost of starting with a larger domain. The following famous result was originally shown by
and Rado using tree arguments (with
lowered to
in the conclusion). We give instead an elementary substructures argument due to Baumgartner, Hajnal and
which proves the stronger version. For
a cardinal let
Theorem 1 (
-Rado) Let
be a regular cardinal and let
Then
for all
![]()
Proof: Let and let
Lemma 2 There is
such that
![]()
![]()
and
![]()
Proof: Start with any with
and
and inductively build a continuous chain
for so that if
then
and
This is possible since
is bounded in
by regularity of
and
Let Then
is as required, by regularity of
Fix as in the lemma. Let
Then is a
-complete ideal over
i.e.:
-
: Notice that
since
is definable in
as the largest cardinal. If
then
so
since
-
; and
implies
- If
and
then
: Let
witness that
Then
since
Thus,
and it witnesses that
In particular,
since clearly
for all
For let
Then so, for some
(since
is
-closed). Fix such
We claim that for any
such that
there is
such that
and
is
-homogeneous. This will suffice, because
is also
-homogeneous (by definition of
) and has order type
To see the claim, it suffices to show, by regularity of that if
is
-homogeneous, then there is
such that
is also
-homogeneous. Fix such
and notice that
Let
Then Since
But then
as witnessed by
Since
we must have that
and in particular there is some
The full version of the -Rado theorem (for partitions of
-sets with
) can be obtained by combining this method with the end-homogeneous sets approach, as in the proof of Ramsey’s theorem in Subsection 2.3 of lecture III.1. One can thus show the following:
Theorem 3 (
-Rado) Let
and
for
Let
and let
be an infinite regular cardinal. Then
-Rado also showed that
cannot be replaced with
in this result. And regarding Theorem 1 from last lecture, one can also prove a more general (non-topological) version:
Theorem 4 (
-Dushnik-Miller) Let
be regular and let
and
Then
![]()
Proof: Argue as before, and use the same notation. Now and we need either a
-homogeneous set of size
or an
-homogeneous set of order type
for some
If
for some
the proof above works, so we can assume that
for all
Since
is
-complete, we then have
Let be a witness so
and
Let
so
and
Then
Let
so and
It follows from elementarity (see below) that
is unbounded in
Since
is regular, this means that
and, by construction, it is 0-homogeneous and we are done.
To prove that is unbounded, notice that if
then
as witnessed, for example, by By elementarity,
so, since was arbitrary,
By elementarity, the same holds in so
is unbounded in
The proofs of Theorems 1 and 3 above require the axiom of choice. However, the proof of Theorem 4 in lecture III.2 requires a choiceless version. I now proceed to establish this version.
Theorem 5 (
) For any set
any ordinal
and any nonzero
there is some initial ordinal
such that
As mentioned in lecture III.2, this version of the -Rado theorem seems to have been rediscovered a few times, by Keisler and Morley in 1967, by Kleinberg and Seiferas in 1973, and by Forster (for
finite) in 2007. I follow the elegant presentation from Keisler-Morley, which also seems to give the optimal bounds. The three arguments are rather similar, using the technique of end-homogeneous sets; the lack of choice actually does not affect very much the argument below:
Proof: Let’s begin with some notation.
- A cardinal will mean here an initial ordinal.
- Given a set
write
for the sup of the cardinals that inject into
Note that we only look at cardinals rather than ordinals, so
does not necessarily coincide with
If
is well-orderable, then the notation coincides with the standard usage:
is the unique cardinal bijectable with
.
- Write
for the first cardinal larger than
even if this is a finite number.
- Given an infinite cardinal
let
be the largest cardinal that can be represented as a union of
many sets of size
Hence,
is either
or
and under choice it coincides with
(The case
was briefly discussed before Homework problem 7 in lecture II.1.)
- By transfinite recursion, define the numbers
for an arbitrary set
and ordinal
as follows:
-
-
is the least cardinal strictly larger than
and at least as large as
- For
limit,
Under choice,
is the cardinality of the result of iterating
many times the power set operation on
i.e.,
-
Let be a set. We will show by induction on
that if
is an infinite cardinal, then
This obviously gives the result.
Note that is well-orderable, as it can be identified in a natural way with a subset of
Letting
be a coloring, it follows that we may as well assume that
The case
is now immediate.
Assume and that the result is valid for
We now describe a tree construction that gives rise to a large end-homogeneous set. We define for each
a function
according to the following requirements:
-
implies
-
is an ordinal,
- Whenever
there is a
such that
Note that by 1 this
is unique. Denote it by
- If
then
is the function
defined by
Note that conditions 1–4 uniquely specify by a straightforward inductive argument. This is because, by 3,
is the domain of
iff
is defined but does not coincide with any
for
Lemma 6 Suppose
is an ordinal and
Then
Proof: If there is an obvious injection from
into the ordinal
so we can identify any function
with domain
with a
-sequence of sequences of elements of
each of these sequences of length at most
Hence, we can identify
with a sequence of length at most
of elements of
Since there are at most
many such sequences.
Since it follows from the lemma that there is some
such that
Fix such
Let note that
and consider the coloring
given by
By the induction hypothesis there is a with
and an
such that
is
-homogeneous for
It is enough to check that is also
-homogeneous for
For this, let
and let
and
Then
and, from conditions 3 and 4 above, it follows that
as well.
Note that this argument also proves Theorem 3 above.
Bibliography
- James Baumgartner, András Hajnal, Stevo
, Extensions of the
-Rado theorem, in Finite and infinite combinatorics in sets and logic, NATO (1991), 1–18.
- Jerome Keisler, Michael Morley, Elementary extensions of models of set theory, Israel J. Math., 6 (1968) 49–65.
Typeset using LaTeX2WP. Here is a printable version of this post.
[…] generalization of the elementary substructures argument used to prove the -Rado Theorem 1 from last lecture. Together with the argument below, this provides us with a nice, relatively short, purely […]
[…] generalization of the elementary substructures argument used to prove the -Rado Theorem 1 from last lecture. Together with the argument below, this provides us with a nice, relatively short, purely […]