Updates
Let me begin with a couple of updates.
In the last Corollary of the Appendix to lecture I.5, I indicate that in we have that
whenever is not
for some infinite limit ordinal
In fact,
holds.
This result is best possible in terms of positive results. In Theorem 11 of the paper by John Hickman listed at the end, it is shown that for any such it is consistent with
that there is an
with
for which
I also want to give an update on the topics discussed in lecture III.3.
and Hajnal asked whether it is possible to have infinite cardinals
such that
Galvin and Prikry showed (see Corollaries 16 and 18 of lecture III.3) that any such must be larger than
and that
Following a nice suggestion of Grigor Sargsyan, we use arguments as in Theorem 9 from lecture III.5 to show that this partition relation cannot hold.
The key is the following:
Lemma 1 If there are infinite cardinals
such that
then for every sufficiently large
there is an elementary embedding
such that
![]()
![]()
and
![]()
Here is a brief sketch:
Proof: By Corollary 20 from lecture III.3, the given relation is equivalent to Consider a
-Skolem function
so that any
closed under
is both closed under
-sequences and an elementary substructure of
Use to define a coloring
by setting
whenever
and
otherwise. By assumption, there is
with
Note that if
is the closure of
under
then
But we can assure that
and the result follows by taking as
the transitive collapse of
One concludes the proof by noting that it is impossible to have such embeddings. For this, it suffices that and that
admits a fixed point past its critical point. One then obtains a contradiction just as in Kunen’s proof that there are no embeddings
see Corollary 9 in lecture III.3.
Similarly, Matthew Foreman has shown that there are no embeddings with
closed under
-sequences. The reason is that any such embedding must admit a fixed point past its critical point, as can be argued from the existence of scales. See the paper by Vickers and Welch listed at the end for a proof of this result.
On the other hand, it is still open whether one can have embeddings such that
computes cofinality
correctly.
1. The Baumgartner-Hajnal theorem
In Theorem 2 of lecture III.5 we showed the -Rado result that
whenever is regular. It is natural to wonder whether stronger results are possible. We restrict ourselves here to the case
Due to time constraints, we state quite a few results without proof.
1.1. Hajnal’s counterexample
In general, we cannot even have
For example, Hajnal showed that this fails under and
showed that it fails in well-known forcing extensions (e.g., after adding one Cohen real). I present here Hajnal’s argument:
Theorem 2 (Hajnal) Let
be regular and assume that
Then
This means that there is a coloring
that neither admits a
-homogeneous bipartite graph with
plus
vertices, nor a
-homogeneous bipartite graph with
vertices below and
vertices above.
From this, one immediately concludes:
Corollary 3 If
is regular and
then
![]()
![]()
Proof: Let enumerate
By transfinite recursion we will define a sequence
of subsets of in terms of which we will then define the coloring
We require that
and define
so that
for all
We start by setting for all
Suppose now that
and
has been defined for all
To define
we use transfinite recursion to define a sequence
of ordinals below and then set
Fix a bijection let
and suppose that
has been defined. Let
If this set is nonempty, let Otherwise, let
This completes the construction of the sequence
hence that of the sequence
and of the coloring
It remains to show that has the stated property. First, we observe the following almost-disjoint property of the sets
Proof: We may assume that Let
be such that
We then have that
since any nonzero with
is not in
by definition of
Next we check that there is no -homogeneous graph of type
In effect, fix
and two ordinals
such that
If
then contradicting Lemma 4.
Now we check that there is no -homogeneous graph of type
Towards a contradiction, suppose that
that
and that
Let
Lemma 5
![]()
Proof: Suppose otherwise. Pick
and let be such that
Pick
and let
be such that
We claim that Hence
and since we obtain a contradiction.
To see that note that:
-
- For any
if
then
and, if
then
- Therefore
has size strictly less than
by regularity of
It follows that
Let enumerate the first
elements of
Now set
so has size
and there is some
such that
Pick and let
be such that
Just as above, we reach a contradiction once we show that
To prove that this is the case, let be such that
Since
is regular, it follows from Lemma 4 that
has size and therefore so does
1.2. Countable ordinals
Hajnal’s result rules out a natural extension of the relation
so we need to look a bit harder for possible extensions. Note that the relation implies immediately that
for any This is because of the following result:
Lemma 6 Any stationary subset of
contains closed subsets of order type
for any countable
![]()
(Of course, we cannot replace with
since there are disjoint stationary sets.)
Proof: Let be a given stationary set, and argue by induction on
that
contains closed copies
of
with
arbitrarily large. (Of course, if the result holds, this must be the case: Given any
, notice that
is stationary, so it must contain a closed copy
of
, and
.)
This strengthened version holds trivially for finite or successor, by induction. So it suffices to show it for
limit, assuming it holds for all smaller ordinals. Define a club
with increasing enumeration
as follows:
Let be strictly increasing and cofinal in
. Since
contains closed copies
of
for all
, with their minima arbitrarily large, by choosing such copies
with
and taking their union, we see that
must contain copies of
, closed in their supremum, with arbitrarily large minimum element. (I am not claiming that
built this way has order type
. For example, if
and
, then
would have order type
; but for sure
is closed in its supremum and has order type at least
. So a suitable initial segment of
is as wanted.)
Let be the supremum of such a copy of
. At limit ordinals
, let
. Once
is defined, find such a copy of
inside
with minimum larger than
, and let
be its supremum.
The set so constructed is club, so it meets
. If they meet in
or in a
, this immediately gives us a closed copy of
inside
. If they meet in a
with
limit, let
be strictly increasing and cofinal in
, and consider an appropriate initial segment of
, where
is a closed copy of
in
.
A direct extension of the relation is briefly discussed in Subsection 1.6. This relation certainly implies
so one natural attempt at extending this result is seeing whether for a fixed
there is a
such that
This is not the case: From Ramsey’s theorem, we know that
however, no countable
satisfies
In fact, more is true:
Proof: Let be an ordering of
in order type
and let
be the corresponding “
” coloring:
Then clearly there can be no -homogeneous set of order type
, while a
-homogeneous set of order type
would give us an infinite
-descending sequence.
Since for all
and all
the best we could hope for is that for any
and any finite
there is an
such that
Note that, trivially,
However, relations of the form
are already significantly harder to achieve. The key to positive results of this kind is to study indecomposable ordinals, those of the form
Theorem 8 Let
be countable, and let
be finite. Suppose that
Then
![]()
![]()
Corollary 9 (
-Milner) If
and
then
Thus
for all
![]()
![]()
For certain ordinals, something stronger is true; for example, Specker showed that
for all finite but the same statement fails if we replace
with
on the other hand, Chang showed that
for all finite The precise characterization of those countable ordinals
such that
for all finite stills seems to be open. Special attention has been given to partition ordinals, these are countable ordinals
such that
Theorem 10 (Galvin-Larson) Any partition ordinal other than
has the form
for some countable
![]()
![]()
The Galvin-Larson result uses the notion of pinning, introduced by Specker:
Definition 11 (Specker) An ordinal
pins an ordinal
in symbols
iff there is a pinning map
that is, a map such that for any
we have that
![]()
The connection of this notion with the partition calculus comes from Specker’s observation that if for
an ordinal and
a cardinal, and if
then
For example, Specker showed that
for
and that
from which it follows that
for
Theorem 12 (Schipperus) If
is indecomposable or the sum of two indecomposable ordinals, then
holds.
![]()
On the other hand, one has:
- If
is the sum of at least four indecomposable ordinals, then
- If
is the sum of at least three indecomposable ordinals, then
- If
is the sum of two indecomposable ordinals, then
- If
and
then
holds.
Items 1–3 of Theorem 13 are due to Schipperus, with 6 instead of 5 in item 3; the stated version of item 3 is due to Larson, and item 4 is due to Darby.
1.3. Non-special linear orders
Another possible extension of the relation for all
comes from replacing
with some other (necessarily uncountable) linear order. A first result of this kind was obtained by
and Rado. Recall that
is the order type of
Theorem 14 (
-Rado)
for all
in fact, whenever
is uncountable,
![]()
Proof: Let be uncountable. Without loss, assume that
is of size
and let
enumerate it. Let
be a given coloring.
Mimicking the proof that for each limit
let’s build a strictly increasing sequence
such that:
-
for all
-
for all
-
is 1-homogeneous for
- Either
or else
for some
and there is no
such that items 1–3 hold with
in place of
If for some limit we have
we are done, as we have found a subset of
of order type
that is
-homogeneous for
We can then assume that
for all limit ordinals
By repeated application of Fodor’s lemma we can then find an uncountable (in fact, stationary) subset
of
consisting of limit ordinals, and such that there is an
with
for all
and there are ordinals
such that
for all
and all
It then follows that whenever and
in
implies
then
is
-homogeneous. Otherwise, if
are in
and
we could take
contradiction.
We have essentially reduced the partition problem to a problem which is solely about ordered sets: It now suffices to show that whenever is an uncountable subset of
then
for all
We prove something stronger; recall that
is the order type of
(Actually, we need something a bit stronger, namely, that there is a subset of
of type
whose indices are also ordered that way. This follows easily by induction from the argument below. We will prove a more general result later, so I will leave this last step as an exercise.)
Proof: Let
and
The coinitiality of and the cofinality of
are both countable, since
and
It follows that
and
are in fact countable. Also,
is a final segment of
and
is an initial segment. Let
so
is uncountable and for any
both
and
are uncountable.
A straightforward recursive construction using the above observation easily gives us that
Applying Lemma 15 to the set we are done.
A careful study of the above argument seems to indicate that the notion below is the key to the “right” generalization of for
The concept was introduced by Galvin, although the name is probably due to
Definition 16 A linear order
is non-special if it is not the union of countably many reverse well-orders, i.e.,
Clearly, any non-special order is uncountable.
Here are some examples of non-special orders:
-
- Suppose that
is an uncountable linear order and that
Then
It follows that
is non-special, since if
is partitioned into countably many pieces, one of them must be uncountable (and does not embed
). In particular, the set of reals or, more generally, any uncountable subset of
is non-special. Because of this example, uncountable linearly ordered sets that embed neither
nor
are called of real type. It easily follows from the argument above that for any such
we have
for all
- Baumgartner has shown that there are non-special orders such that
embeds into any uncountable subset. For example, for each limit
let
be cofinal in
of order type
Denote by
the
-th member in the increasing enumeration of
and set
for
countable limit ordinals iff, letting
be least such that
then
Galvin noted that Lemma 7 could be improved as follows:
Proof: Consider an arbitrary partition of into
many pieces
; we must show that at least one of them admits a subset of order type
. Define
by setting, for
,
iff there are
such that
and
. Clearly
does not admit a 0-homogeneous set of order type
. By assumption, it must therefore admit a
-homogeneous set of order type
. All but finitely many of its members must then belong to the same
, and thus
contains a subset of order type
, as wanted.
The Baumgartner-Hajnal theorem is the statement that a strong converse to Lemma 17 holds.
Theorem 18 (Baumgartner-Hajnal) If
is non-special, then
for all
and
![]()
![]()
In Subsection 1.5, I present a proof of Theorem 18 in the particular case that The argument I will show is very recent and due to Clinton Conley. It also provides us with additional information about colorings of
and I address this as well.
1.4. Partial orders
The original proof of the Baumgartner-Hajnal theorem used forcing. More precisely, the result was shown under the additional assumption of and then an absoluteness result is invoked to guarantee that it follows without this axiom. This involves two steps: Assume
and let
be a finite coloring of
Force
(plus
) the usual way, so the forcing notion involved is ccc, and
is preserved. In the extension,
still holds, and therefore
- We may assume that
is infinite. Let
be a bijection. Use
and
to define a tree of height
any (infinite) branch through which gives a homogeneous subset of
for
of order type
The tree is defined in the ground model, but it is ill-founded in the forcing extension. Well-foundedness is absolute (being equivalent to the existence of a ranking function) and therefore the tree must also be ill-founded in the ground model. It follows that there is, in
a homogeneous subset of
for
of type
This is true for all
and all colorings
and therefore
- More delicately, one needs to verify that, indeed,
still holds in the forcing extension. This uses that the forcing involved is ccc.
It is natural to wonder whether Theorem 18 admits a forcing-free proof. Galvin found such an argument, and noticed that in a natural way one is led to consider not just linear orders but partial orders. Somewhat later, extended the result to this setting:
Theorem 19 (
) Assume that
is a non-special partial order. Then
for all
and all
![]()
![]()
As with the original argument of Baumgartner and Hajnal, ‘s proof uses forcing, and I do not know of a way of removing this need. For the case
a new (forcing-free) proof has been recently found by Foreman and Hajnal; it is a significant generalization of the elementary substructures argument used to prove the
-Rado Theorem 1 from last lecture. Together with the argument below, this provides us with a nice, relatively short, purely combinatorial proof of the Baumgartner-Hajnal theorem for linear orders. The Foreman-Hajnal result can be found in the survey by Hajnal and Larson listed in the references at the end.
This is not yet the end of the story. has shown that
implies
for all
It is not known yet whether the same follows from
I believe the best known result in this direction is due to Hirschorn, who showed that under
one has
1.5. The Baumgartner-Hajnal theorem
I follow closely the note by Conley listed in the references at the end. Our goal is to show that if is a non-special linear order such that
then
for all
and all
Fix a linearly ordered set For sets
say that
iff for all
and
(The notation
is commonly used, but we already use
to indicate that
embeds into
)
Fix a proper ideal of subsets of
and use terms like small, positive, and large, in the usual way: A small set is a member of
A positive set is one not in
A large set is one whose complement is in
A set
is large in
iff
The quantifier
means “for all positive
” Similarly,
means “there exists a positive
”
Say that positive sets split iff any positive set contains positive sets
and
with
below
Definition 20 For
a coloring and
say that
is an
-compatible pair iff
and
are both positive subsets of
and for all positive
the set
is large in
![]()
Note that if is positive and
is a coloring, then for any
one of
and
must be positive. Definition 20 asserts that there is a “coherent” way of (almost) always picking the same color that gives us a positive set. One can strengthen this notion as follows:
Definition 21 For
a coloring and
say that
is an
-focused pair iff
and
are positive subsets of
and for all
the set
is large in
Note that an -focused pair is
-compatible, and that the notions are hereditary, in the sense that if
is
-compatible, and
and
are both positive, then
is also
-compatible. Similarly with
-focused instead of
-compatible.
Lemma 22 Suppose that
is a coloring, and that
are positive. Then there are positive sets
and
such that either
is
-focused for some
or
is
-compatible for both
and
![]()
Proof: Consider the statement
Case 1: It is true, as witnessed by
and
Let
and notice that is
-focused.
Case 2: It is false. We then have
But this is equivalent to
(Otherwise, fixing counterexamples and
the complement
of the displayed set would contradict the displayed statement immediately preceding it.) Consequently,
is
-compatible for both
and
Note that the notion of an -compatible pair depends on the order in which we list the sets
and
Definition 23 For
a coloring and
say that
is an
-compatible pair iff
is
-compatible, and
is
-compatible.
The following three consequences of Lemma 22 are straightforward; for Lemma 26, use Corollary 25 and a density argument.
Corollary 24 Let
be a coloring, and suppose that
are positive. Then there exist positive sets
and
such that either
is
-focused for some
or
is
-compatible for some
![]()
Corollary 25 Let
be a coloring, and suppose that
are positive. Then there exist positive sets
and
such that
is
-compatible for some
![]()
![]()
Lemma 26 Suppose that positive sets split, and let
be a coloring. Then there is a positive
and
such that whenever
is positive, then we may find positive subsets
and
of
with
below
such that that the pair
is
-compatible.
![]()
In the setting of Lemma 26, it follows that, by passing to a positive subset of we may assume that the coloring
is
-splitting, in the following sense:
Definition 27 Assume that positive sets split, and let
be a coloring. For
say that
is
-splitting iff for any positive
there are positive subsets
and
with
below
such that
is
-compatible.
Lemma 28 Let
be an
-splitting coloring. Then there are positive sets
and
and an element
such that:
is below
and
is below
![]()
is
-compatible,
and
![]()
Proof: Use twice that is
-splitting, and find positive sets
with
below
and
below
such that
and
are all
-compatible.
Since is
-compatible, then the set
is large in Similarly,
is large in
It follows that Let
be in this intersection. Now set
and
Then is as wanted.
It will be important in what follows to study colorings of It turns out to be convenient to have a representation of
different from the standard one. For this, simply recall that any countable linear order dense in itself and without end points is isomorphic to
Extend the lexicographic order on each to a linear order on
by setting
for
iff
where
is the first coordinate on which they differ, adopting the convention that
undefined
The following is obvious from the characterization of
just mentioned:
Lemma 29
![]()
![]()
For let
denote its length. We now define four colorings of
Definition 30 For
let
be the map given by
These colorings are rather special. and
are constant.
and
do not admit homogeneous sets of type
admits a 1-homogeneous set of type
and
admits a 1-homogeneous set of type
These two colorings are standard counterexamples to a version of Ramsey’s theorem on
in which the homogeneous set has order type
Before hand, we knew that such counterexamples were to be expected, since
by Lemma 7.
Theorem 31 (Conley) Suppose that positive sets split, and let
be a coloring. Then there are
and an order-preserving injection
such that
Proof: As explained after Lemma 26, we may assume that is
-splitting for some
We now proceed to embed
into
For this, we recursively construct for each
a function
so that the functions
are compatible as
varies and, letting
then
is as wanted. To guarantee this, we construct in addition for each
a positive set
so that
-
is
-compatible whenever
are in
and
- For all
whenever
At stage use the splitting assumption and Lemma 28 to find
and positive sets
and
such that
-
is below
is below
-
and
and
-
is
-compatible,
and set
Suppose that the construction has been carried out through stage Stage
is completed by going from left to right in
To begin with, by the assumption of compatibility, we may assume that there is a set
large in
such that for all
and all
with
the set
is positive. Apply Lemma 28 to as in stage
to obtain
and an
-compatible pair
Then, replace each
with the positive set
Suppose now that we have defined
and
for all
smaller than
By the assumption of compatibility, we may assume that for all
and all
with
the set
is positive, and that for all and all
with
the set
is positive.
Apply Lemma 28 to as before, and obtain
and an
-compatible pair
Now, for each
with
replace
with
and, for each with
replace
with
At the end of the construction, we obtain an order-preserving injection and now we proceed to verify that it is as desired. Fix
If the construction defined
before
then
belongs to the refined version of
constructed right after
was defined. But then
and we are done.
The following canonization result is immediate:
Corollary 32 Suppose that
is an arbitrary coloring. Then there are
and
such that
![]()
Proof: Apply Theorem 31 to and the ideal
The above results (as well as the results in the remainder of this subsection) hold for any finite number of colors. In this setting, the only change we obtain is that the basis of colorings in the canonization result has size larger than four, but they are all either constant functions or of the form for
Corollary 33 (
-Rado) The partition relation
holds, i.e., any coloring of
with two colors black and red either admits a black-homogeneous copy of
or else it admits an infinite red-homogeneous set.
![]()
Note also that cannot be improved to either
or
Corollary 34 (Galvin) For any
we have
i.e., for any coloring of
with finitely many colors, there is a copy of
that uses at most two colors.
![]()
This is an example of a so-called “rainbow” Ramsey theorem. The ultimate result in this direction is due to D. Devlin:
Definition 35 Let
be the Taylor series expansion of
about
Define the sequence
of odd tangent numbers by
so
Theorem 36 (Devlin)
- For every positive integer
we have
![]()
- However, for any
we have
![]()
We can now deduce the promised version of the Baumgartner-Hajnal theorem from Theorem 31.
Corollary 37 Suppose that
is
-additive and that positive sets split. Let
be a coloring. Then, for all
there exists a homogeneous set for
of order type
![]()
Proof: By Theorem 31, if we can find an -splitting, positive set
then in fact
admits a homogeneous set for
of order type
By Corollary 24 and a density argument, we may then assume that there is an such that every positive set
can split into positive sets
and
with
below
and
an
-focused pair.
We now proceed by induction on to show that
admits an
-homogeneous subset of type
Assume the result for all Suppose first that
Split
into sets
below
where
is
-focused. Let
be
-homogeneous. For each
the set
is large in Since
is
-additive, we may find an
in the intersection of all these sets and, clearly,
is
-homogeneous and of type
Suppose now that is a limit ordinal, and let
be increasing and cofinal in
Split
several times to find
such that each pair with
is
-focused. By the inductive hypothesis, find an
-homogeneous set
As in the previous case, refine each
with
in such a way that
Now continue inductively, finding an -homogeneous set
and refining all
with
Finally, let Then
is
-homogeneous and of type
Again, Corollary 37 holds for colorings into any finite number of colors.
Corollary 38 (Baumgartner-Hajnal) Suppose that
is a non-special linearly ordered set and that
Then
for all
and
![]()
Proof: Let By Corollary 37, it suffices to show that positive sets split.
Bearing in mind the proof of Theorem 14, consider a positive and let
and
Since then
has cofinality
and it follows that
We are done once we show that
because then we can replace
with
and note that for all
both
and
are positive.
We are not assuming that so the argument is slightly more delicate than in Theorem 14. Let
be a strictly decreasing, coinitial sequence in
For each
let
be a partition without homogeneous sets of type
For
let
be the least ordinal
such that
Now define
by and note that
witnesses
It would be interesting to find a unified proof of the full Baumgartner-Hajnal theorem following the methods of this subsection, and to see whether these methods can be extended to provide a combinatorial proof of ‘s Theorem 19.
1.6. The topological Baumgartner-Hajnal theorem
An easy variation of the argument used to show Theorem 14 gives us that
whenever is an uncountable subset of
meaning that any coloring
either admits an infinite increasing
-homogeneous set, or else it admits a closed subset of order type
that is
-homogeneous. The following extension was recently obtained by Schipperus; it solves questions of Laver and Weiss:
Theorem 39 (Schipperus)
and
for any uncountable
any
and any
![]()
![]()
Once again, Schipperus’s argument uses forcing and absoluteness. It is easy to see that being non-special is not enough to imply the result, and I do not know of a more general setting for which Schipperus’s theorem holds; see his paper (listed below) for details.
I do not know whether under or
one can prove that
for all
and
1.7. Partitions of triples
Finally, I would like to close with a couple of words on an extension of a different kind, namely, what occurs when we color triples rather than pairs.
Theorem 40 (Jones) Let
be a non-special partial order. Then
and
for each
![]()
- For
item 1 can be improved to
for all
![]()
It has been conjectured by Jones and others that if is a non-special partial order, then
for all
and
The assumption on
cannot be weakened, in light of the following result; a similar obstacle holds for partial orders:
Theorem 41 If
is a linear order,
is an infinite cardinal, and
then
![]()
![]()
Bibliography
- James Baumgartner, A new class of order types, Annals of Mathematical Logic, 9 (1976), 187–222.
- James Baumgartner, András Hajnal, A proof (involving Martin’s axiom) of a partition relation, Fund. Math., 78 (3) (1973), 193–203.
- Clinton Conley, Colors and ideals: An artistic extravaganza, preprint.
- Paul
András Hajnal, Attila Máté, Richard Rado, Combinatorial set theory: Partition relations for cardinals, North-Holland, (1984).
- András Hajnal, Jean Larson, Partition relations, in Handbook of set theory, Matthew Foreman, Akihiro Kanamori, eds., to appear.
- John L. Hickman,
-minimal lattices, Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 26 (2) (1980), 181–191.
- Albin Jones, Partitioning triples and partially ordered sets, Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 136 (5) (May 2008), 1823–1830.
- Rene Schipperus, Countable partition ordinals, PhD thesis, University of Colorado, Boulder; Richard Laver, advisor, (1999).
- Rene Schipperus, The topological Baumgartner-Hajnal theorem, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1090/S0002-9947-2012-04990-7
- John Vickers, Philip Welch, On Elementary Embeddings of an Inner Model to the Universe, The Journal for Symbolic Logic, 66 (3) (2001), 1090–1116.
- Neil Williams, Combinatorial set theory, North-Holland (1977).
Typeset using LaTeX2WP. Here is a printable version of this post.
Silly typo: In Corollary 9, the last
should be 
In the proof of Theorem 31, in two instances I write
or
It should be
in both cases.
A nice remark of Galvin shows that Baumgartner-Hajnal for
follows from Clinton’s result in 1.5, so we now have a very nice, easy to remember, short, and purely combinatorial proof of the full Baumgartner-Hajnal theorem for linear orders.
It is remark 1 (pg 714) in F. Galvin “On a partition theorem of Baumgartner and Hajnal,” Colloquia Mathematica Societatis Janos Bolyai, vol 10. Infinite and Finite Sets, Keszthely (Hungary), 1973, 711-729.
Let
be any non-special linear order of size
that does not embed
so from Clinton’s result, Baumgartner-Hajnal holds for
Let
be an injection.
Given a finite
a coloring
and an infinite countable ordinal
let
be given by:
iff 
iff 
1.
2.
There is then some
subset of
of type
-homogeneous for
for some 
Notice
cannot be
since 
Then
is a subset of
of type
and is
-homogeneous for
for some 
[This also shows that one cannot improve Clinton's result to show that if
is non-special and does not embed
and
then
admits a homogeneous set of type
]
WordPress has added a few changes to the way LaTeX is compiled in their posts, and this has introduced hundreds of error messages through dozens of previous entries. It will take me a while to fix them.This has happened before, which is making me reconsider whether to keep the formatting I’ve been using. Any suggestions? I may even simply post pdf files if an entry has too much LaTeX into it to avoid having to revise the code every few months.
[Update: The issue seems to have been resolved.]
Corollary 33 is in fact due to Erdos and Rado.
“A partition calculus in set theory”, Bull AMS, 62(1956), 427-489.
Click to access 1956-02.pdf
Hi Peter,
Thanks! I am slowly editing these notes, and in my current TeX file I had the right reference, but (even though I mentioned it to Conley) somehow missed mentioning it here.
Incidentally, there is a proof of Theorem 19 that doesn’t involve any forcing. Essentially, one can generalize the Foreman-Hajnal method for
to arbitrary non-special trees. This is sufficient by a result of 
Hi Albin,
This sounds very nice! I would be grateful if you have a write-up (even if not entirely polished) that you can send me, or a reference. (Last I visited your page, what I think would be the relevant paper was listed as ‘in progress’.)
I like very much your work on colorings of triples, by the way.
Oddly enough, I guess, I only ever tried for the result on non-special trees, thinking that Galvin had already produced a forcing-free proof for linear orders and figuring that a proof for non-special trees would cover all bases in one go.
I discovered my argument independently of Foreman and Hajnal’s results (and nearly simultaneously). I presented it in a seminar just over ten years ago now. I *might* be able to dig up my notes, but probably not.
I did start writing up the result, but stopped midway through because I thought that the Foreman and Hajnal proof was less messy, better for generalization, and would still generalize from
to non-special-trees directly.
I still have the unfinished write-up. It *might* be readable as is, but if you’re really interested in the proof, I’d like to try to finish writing it up right. (I say “try” only because I’m a slow writer.)
I’m glad you like the results on triples. Thank you. I’m very happy to have made even a little progress on those problems.
Albin: Many thanks for the comment. I’m definitely interested in the result. Would you email me the current version? Of course, if you rather I wait for a final version, that is fine as well.
Theorem 39 is now available online.
DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-2012-04990-7.
Oh, yes. Thanks! (Updated accordingly.)