Here is quiz 7.
Solutions follow.
Problem 1 asks us to prove that, for all natural numbers we have
There are several ways of showing this. I present two proofs, one using the well-ordering principle (least counterexample), and the other arguing by induction.
Proof 1: Using the well-ordering principle, one proceeds as follows: Suppose the result is false. This means that there is a natural for which the identity fails, and therefore (since the set
of naturals for which the identity fails is non-empty) there is a least natural
for which the identity fails. This means several things:
- If
is a natural number,
We begin by noticing that because
meaning that the identity holds in this case.
It follows that is also a natural number. By item 2, we then have that
The plan is now to somehow transform this equality into the equality that item 1 claims must fail. To do this, the most direct route seems to be to add to both sides of the displayed equation. We have
We have indeed shown that item 1 is false. This is a contradiction, and we conclude that our assumption (that the identity fails for some natural ) is false, meaning of course that the identity holds for all natural numbers, as we wanted to prove.
Proof 2: Using induction, one argues as follows: First, we show that the identity is true when This is indeed the case, since
Now we assume that the identity holds for some number meaning that
We need to somehow conclude that also To do this, we can start with the identity for
that we are assuming is true, and add
to both sides. We obtain
Now we observe that and we conclude that the identity also holds for
as we wanted to show.
By induction, we conclude that the identity holds for all natural numbers.
[Note that both proofs are very similar, as was to be expected.]
Problem 2 starts by defining a sequence by recursion: We set and, in general,
for all naturals
We are asked to prove that
for all
Once again, one can argue by either the well-ordering principle, or induction. I present here a proof using induction. First, we consider the case We have
which is obviously larger than
Assuming now that we need to prove that
as well. For this, we use that
from which it follows, using the inductive assumption, that
This is what we needed to prove. By induction, we conclude that for all
Remark: One can also prove that induction that for all
i.e., that the sequence is decreasing. To see this, note that
Assuming that
we then have that
then
and so
But this means (using the recursive definition of the sequence) that
By induction, the sequence is decreasing.
A fundamental result in calculus is that a decreasing sequence that is bounded below must converge. We can now easily compute In effect, let
Then, of course, we also have
Using the recursive definition of the sequence, we then have
The equality
quickly gives us that
As a matter of fact, we can show that if is any real number, and we define the sequence
recursively, by setting
for all
then:
- If
then
for all
and the sequence is decreasing, meaning that
for all
- If
then
for all
and the sequence is increasing, meaning that
for all
- If
then
for all
- In all three cases,
Though the example presented here is simple, this technique of computing limits of sequences by studying their behavior using induction, is actually very useful in higher calculus (mathematical analysis).
Problem 3 asks us to identify the flaw in the following wrong argument:
Theorem. All natural numbers are equal.
Proof. We argue by induction on
that if
and
then
![]()
The case
holds, because if
and
are natural numbers, then in fact
Suppose then that the result holds for
and consider natural numbers
with
Then
and, by the inductive assumption, it follows that
But then
![]()
The argument is presented as a proof by induction, with the base case and the inductive case indicated. If indeed both cases are argued correctly, the conclusion will follow. This means that the flaw is either in the proof of the base case or of the inductive case.
The base case, however, is proved correctly: If are natural numbers, then
If we are also given that
then we have
and
so indeed
It follows that the flaw must lie somewhere within the inductive case. Now, if then indeed
Also, if
then also
And, finally, if it is indeed the case that we can apply the inductive assumption then, from
we are forced to conclude that
It follows that the flaw is in assuming that the inductive assumption applies. Recall that the inductive assumption is:
If
and
then
And we are using it with and
Since
the only place we have left, and thus the place where the problem should reside, is in affirming that
We see that this is, as expected, a problem, because if and
then we cannot conclude that both
as well. Of course, one of
equals
and
but, for all we know, we could have
and
Then
and the inductive assumption does not apply to
since they are not both natural numbers.