Write to indicate that there is an injection from
into
, and
to mean that either
, or else there is a surjection from
onto
. It is a result of Kuratowski that (provably in
) if
, then in fact
, and therefore
. This appears as Théorème B in pages 94-95 of
Alfred Tarski. Sur les ensembles finis, Fund. Math. 6 (1924), 45–95.
To prove this result, note that it suffices to find a countably infinite family of disjoint subsets of . Suppose
is an injection of
into
. These sets induce a partition of
: Consider the equivalence classes of the relation
iff
.
It is natural to attempt to show that these equivalence classes can be enumerated. Of course, the class of is completely specified by the list of values of
such that
, but this list may be “wasteful” in the sense that it may contain redundant information. For example, if
, and we know that
, then we automatically know that
, and there is no need to include
in our list if we already included
. (On the other hand, if all we know is that
then including
in the list is certainly providing us with more information.) This suggests to assign to each
the set
defined recursively as follows: Let
be least such that
, if it exists. If
is defined, let
be least such that
and
, if it exists, and note that this is the same as requiring that
. Similarly, if
is defined, let
be least such that
, and
, if it exists, etc.
Clearly, for any ,
iff
. There are now two possibilities:
- Case 1. For some
, the set
is infinite.
In this case, we are done (and we do not even need to bother enumerating the classes), because the sequence
is a countably infinite collection of non-empty disjoint subsets of .
- Case 2. All sets
are finite.
In this case we are done as well, because there is a (canonical) bijection between and
, which means that we have enumerated the equivalence classes (and, of course, there are infinitely many, since the sets
are all distinct, and each is a union of equivalence classes).
This argument, though similar to Kuratowski’s original approach, is due to Halbeisen and Shelah, and their approach can be generalized to study other situations. See
Lorenz Halbeisen, and Saharon Shelah. Consequences of arithmetic for set theory, J. Symbolic Logic 59 (1), (1994), 30–40. MR1264961 (95c:03128).
Kuratowski’s original proof is as follows:
Let be a countable collection of distinct subsets of
. It suffices to show that there is a countably infinite collection of non-empty pairwise disjoint subsets of
. This is certainly the case if there is an infinite descending chain
where each
is the intersection of finitely many sets
. Suppose that this is not the case. We claim that there must exist a set
such that:
is the intersection of finitely many sets
,
, and
- For all
, either
or
.
In effect, if no such set exists, an easy induction produces a sequence
of indices such that for any
,
, contrary to our assumption. From condition 3., it follows that there is a sequence
such that either
for all
, or
for all
.
Let , where
for each
. Then
is a countable collection of nonempty sets, all of them disjoint from
. We can then iterate the procedure above, and either find a descending sequence
of subsets of
, or a set
satisfying conditions 1-3 with respect to the sets
.
Continue this way inductively. Either at some stage some such decreasing sequence of sets is obtained, and we are done, or else, we have built a sequence
of nonempty pairwise disjoint subsets of
, and again we are done.
Does the result extend immediately to larger aleph numbers? Or do we need to assume some dependent choice holds, and some “inaccessibility”?
Well, in the meantime here is a counterexample: Let
be
-amorphous in a model where
. Every function from
into a well-ordered codomain must have a countable range, therefore
cannot be surjected onto
, but
has countably infinite subsets and therefore its power set has a subset of size
.