116c- Lecture 3

We verified the “surjective” version of Cantor’s theorem: If f:{\mathcal P}(X)\to X then f is not injective. A curious weakness of the standard diagonal proof is that the argument is not entirely constructive: We considered the set A=\{a\in X:\exists Z\,(a=f(Z)\notin Z)\} and showed that there is some set Z\ne A such that f(Z)=f(A).

Question. Can one define such a set Z?

As a consequence of the results we will prove on well-orderings, we will be able to provide a different proof where the pair of distinct sets verifying that f is not injective is definable. (Definability is an issue we will revisit a few times.)

We proved the trichotomy theorem for well-orderings, defined ordinals, and showed that {\sf ORD}=\{ x : x \mbox{ is an ordinal}\} is not a set (the Burali-Forti paradox).

Advertisement

4 Responses to 116c- Lecture 3

  1. Domenic says:

    Although I understand Cantor’s theorem and the “surjective version” well enough separately, and I even see how they are essentially saying the same thing, I don’t really understand the preamble that you were providing before presenting this version.

    That is, I don’t understand why we would consider this version to be a “surjective” version of Cantor’s theorem, since it’s dealing with the nonexistence of injective functions. I also don’t understand the connection to the axiom of choice, and how the fact that a surjection A –> B corresponds (with choice) to an injection B –> A plays any part in this theorem.

    My guess is that there’s a really obvious surjection implicit somewhere in the two statements, which would put everything in the right context, and I’m just missing it.

    Thanks!

  2. The “usual” version of Cantor’s result is that no injection f:x\to{\mathcal P}(x) is onto. The “surjective” version would say that no surjection g:{\mathcal P}(x)\to x is into.

    It just so happens that the argument used in the first case does not actually use that f is an injection, we actually show that no such f is onto. And, similarly, in the second case, we end up not needing to assume that g is a surjection. I suppose one could just as well call the f version the “surjective version” and the g one the “injective version,” but I believe the common usage is as I have it.

    At the heart of both arguments is the simple diagonalization coming from wondering whether A\notin f(A) or g(Z)\notin Z (for appropriate A,Z), and it is in that sense that both arguments are more or less “the same.”

    As for Choice: In Tuesday we will show the fact you mention, that if there is a surjection from A onto B then there is an injection from B into A. So, with choice, both statements “A surjects onto B” and “B injects into A” are the same, and we could use either to define the relation |B|\le|A|. Without choice, these statements are not equivalent, and we could have a different notion |B|\le^*|A| if there is a surjection from A onto B.

    What we showed is that Cantor’s argument gives |x|<|{\mathcal P}(x)| and
    also |x|<^*|{\mathcal P}(x)|, so that x is less than {\mathcal P}(x) *no matter* which version of “less than” one chooses.

    However, I would go further and say that the version one wants is the \le version rather than the \le^* one, since the Schröder-Bernstein theorem holds for this version.

    Question. Does Schröder-Bernstein hold for \le^*?

    (Of course, yes if we assume choice, but the question is whether it holds in ZF.)

  3. Domenic says:

    Wait, that made perfect sense the first time I read it, but then I sat down to formalize it and realized I must be missing something. I’m pretty sure that a straight translation of your first paragraph gives…

    “Usual version”: f injective => neg (f surjective)
    “Surjective version”: g surjective => neg(f injective)

    Um, aren’t these just contrapositives?

  4. I fear I failed to explain myself.

    We proved two different theorems. Theorem 1 says that no map f:x\to{\mathcal P}(x) is surjective. Theorem 2 says that no map g:{\mathcal P}(x)\to x is injective.

    And we shouldn’t call them `injective’ or `surjective’ versions of Cantor’s result any longer, as this seems to be misleading.

    I agree with you, the first paragraph says the same thing twice. But we actually obtained two theorems from our analysis.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

%d bloggers like this: